In the 1780s the anatomist Vincenzo Malacarne discussed the possibility of testing experimentally whether experience can induce significant changes in the brain. Malacarne imagined taking two littermate animals and giving intensive training to one while the other received none, then dissecting their brains to see whether the trained animal had more folds in the cerebellum than the untrained one. This experimental design somewhat anticipated one used 180 years later by Mark R. Rosenzweig at the University of California, Berkeley. This paper explores some methodological aspects of the case study just outlined by pointing out that our grounds for being interested in it are neither merely neuroscientific (for, strictly speaking, Malacarne’s proposal was false) nor narrowly historical (for there is no causal chain linking Malacarne’s ideas to Rosenzweig’s experiment). Rather, the really interesting point here is to what extent Malacarne’s ideas are similar to Rosenzweig’s, a point that we can better investigate by employing certain conceptual tools borrowed typically (but not exclusively) from (a certain kind of) philosophy. If we do not handle the analogy with care, however, we run the risk of ‘discovering’ nothing but void platitudes or anachronistically misleading common features.

Conceptual Mediation. Philosophy between the History of Physiology and Contemporary Neuroscience

TRIPODI, Paolo
2014-01-01

Abstract

In the 1780s the anatomist Vincenzo Malacarne discussed the possibility of testing experimentally whether experience can induce significant changes in the brain. Malacarne imagined taking two littermate animals and giving intensive training to one while the other received none, then dissecting their brains to see whether the trained animal had more folds in the cerebellum than the untrained one. This experimental design somewhat anticipated one used 180 years later by Mark R. Rosenzweig at the University of California, Berkeley. This paper explores some methodological aspects of the case study just outlined by pointing out that our grounds for being interested in it are neither merely neuroscientific (for, strictly speaking, Malacarne’s proposal was false) nor narrowly historical (for there is no causal chain linking Malacarne’s ideas to Rosenzweig’s experiment). Rather, the really interesting point here is to what extent Malacarne’s ideas are similar to Rosenzweig’s, a point that we can better investigate by employing certain conceptual tools borrowed typically (but not exclusively) from (a certain kind of) philosophy. If we do not handle the analogy with care, however, we run the risk of ‘discovering’ nothing but void platitudes or anachronistically misleading common features.
2014
40
4
533
544
http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/01916599.2013.826432#.VImQcDGK29w
Paolo Tripodi
File in questo prodotto:
File Dimensione Formato  
Conceptual Mediation - 2013.pdf

Accesso riservato

Tipo di file: PDF EDITORIALE
Dimensione 130.87 kB
Formato Adobe PDF
130.87 kB Adobe PDF   Visualizza/Apri   Richiedi una copia

I documenti in IRIS sono protetti da copyright e tutti i diritti sono riservati, salvo diversa indicazione.

Utilizza questo identificativo per citare o creare un link a questo documento: https://hdl.handle.net/2318/139880
Citazioni
  • ???jsp.display-item.citation.pmc??? ND
  • Scopus 0
  • ???jsp.display-item.citation.isi??? 0
social impact